i like Να έχεις μια όμορφη μέρα και να είσαι ζεστά ☺️you are going to meet.
Σάββατο 1 Απριλίου 2017
“Presumptuous Philosopher” and “Beauty the High Roller” form a Scylla and a
Charybdis, which we must avoid, and yet it looks like the only way to satisfy the
constraints from these thought experiments involves violating Bayesian
conditionalization.15 I believe, however, that this sacrifice is not necessary. The matter is
somewhat subtle.
Suppose that Beauty will be told after awakening on Monday that it is Monday.
The situation is then different from the one described above. It must instead be
represented as follows:
w1: h1 h1m [The “heads” world]
w2: t1 t1m t2 [The “tails” world]
The situation we are confronting involves five possible agent-parts, not three. The added
terms, “h1m” and “t1m”, denote the agent-parts of Beauty that know that it is Monday (in
the heads and the tails world, respectively). Let us retain the P unchanged (i.e. the
credence function for Beauty at the times when she is unaware that it is Monday). Now
consider more carefully Constraint P+, which seemed like it was a constraint on the P+
(i.e. the credence function that Beauty has when she knows that it is Monday). Constraint
P+ contains the expression “H1 ∨ T1”. But this expression does not describe what Beauty
knows after she has learnt that it is Monday, for at that point she should set:
P+(H1) = 0 P+(T1) = 0
This is because at that point Beauty knows that her current agent-part is either h1m or
t1m. The information she has just obtained is therefore not (H1 ∨ T1), but rather (H1M ∨
T1M), where H1M is the centered proposition expressed by “My current agent-part is
h1m” and T1M is the centered proposition expressed by “My current agent-part is t1m”.
The correct formulation of Constraint P+ is therefore as follows:
P+(HEADS | H1M ∨ T1M) = 1/2 Constraint P+ [corrected]
This correction eliminates the conflict with Constraint P and allows us to avoid violating
Bayesian conditionalization. The corrected Constraint P+ is precisely what we need to
save Beauty from ruin in the High Roller thought experiment.
One may still wonder what conditional credence Beauty should assign, before
being informed about it being Monday, to HEADS given that she is currently an agentpart
that knows that it is Monday:
P(HEADS | H1M ∨ T1M) = ?
However, there is no need to assign a value to this expression. Note that
15 It has been argued that we should indeed violate conditionalization in the Sleeping Beauty problem
(Kierland and Monton). Kierland and Monton argue for the 1/3 answer on grounds which they claim do not
lead to the counterintuitive result in the Beauty and Doppelganger. Their position thus diverges
significantly from Lewis’s 1/2 view.
11
P(HEADS | H1M ∨ T1M) = P(HEADS & [H1M ∨ T1M]) / P(H1M ∨ T1M)
Since P(H1M ∨ T1M) = 0, this expression is undefined. And so it should be.16
Let us take a step back and consider the point more generally. Whenever an agent
receives some evidence E, we could distinguish the earlier agent-part, α–
, that lacked this
evidence, and the later agent-part, α+
, which has come to possess it. According to the
reasoning just described, we cannot automatically conclude that the conditional
probability P(X | E & “I am currently α– “), conditionalized on E, yields the correct
posterior credence that α+
should assign to X. Only if
P(X | E & “I am currently α– “) = P+
(X | E & “I am currently α+ ”),
can the kinematics be represented in the simplified form P+
(X) = P(X | E). This standard
representation is thus elliptic as it omits some changes in indexical information.
In ordinary cases, such changes in indexical information are irrelevant to the
hypotheses being considered and can hence be safely ignored. The standard elliptic
representation of Bayesian conditionalization can then be used without danger. In certain
special cases, however, such delicate changes in indexical information can be relevant,
and it is then crucial to recognize and make explicit the hidden intermediary step.
Sleeping Beauty, on the model proposed here, turns out to be just such a special case.
To recapitulate, I have argued that a Bayesian can coherently accept both
Constraint P and the corrected Constraint P+, even though superficially this seems to
violate Bayesian conditionalization. The reason why we not only can but should accept
both these constraints was given earlier: to avoid the counterintuitive consequences that
follow if either of these constraints is violated, as shown by the “Presumptuous
Philosopher” and the “Beauty the High Roller” thought experiments.
The long-run frequency argument
One other important argument for the 1/3 view needs to be examined as it might be
thought to pose a problem for the hybrid model. The discussion of this argument will also
serve to further elucidate how the proposed model works.
A proponent of the 1/3 view could argue that Sleeping Beauty awakened ought to
have credence 1/3 in HEADS because if the experiment were repeated many times, then
approximately 1/3 of all her awakenings would be heads-awakenings (and 2/3 would be
tails-awakenings). In the infinite limit, this ratio would, with probability 1, be approached
arbitrarily closely. This argument could be buttressed by introducing betting
considerations. In the infinite limit, Beauty would have to assign credence 1/3 to
HEADS, else she would be guaranteed a loss if she put her money where her mouth is.
For a betting argument to have any bite, the hypothesized bookie must have the
same information as Beauty. If a bet were only offered on the Monday awakening in each
run of the experiment, and if both the bookie and Beauty knew this, then Beauty could
16 The model used here presupposes that agent-parts know what their evidence is. This simplifying
assumption may be inappropriate in certain cases, but we shall not here discuss how such cases should be
modeled.
12
infer from the fact that she was offered a bet that it was Monday. According to the hybrid
model, she should then assign credence 1/2 to the proposition that the coin will fall heads
in that trial. This will match the long-run frequency of bets that she will win, so in this
case betting considerations pose no problem.
The betting argument therefore requires that Beauty be offered a bet each time she
is awakened. Then she cannot infer what day it is from the fact that she is being offered a
bet. In this case, in the long run, Beauty would be expected to lose 2/3 of her bets if she
consistently bet on heads. How does this square with the prescription of the hybrid model
that Beauty, upon awakening (but before learning which day it is) assigns credence 1/2 to
heads?
One possible response to this argument is to deny that betting considerations
provide a valid guide to credence assignment in the present case. Since there would be a
different number of bets placed depending on how the coin fell, one might regard the test
as unfair.17 In support of this response one may note that the presumptuous philosopher
would also be vindicated if we assumed that an agent-part’s credence should be
determined by the betting-odds at which the expected net gains and losses of the
collective of all his duplicate agent-parts would be zero. Since there would be a trillion
times more duplicates of the agent-part if theory T2 is true then if T1 is true, each agentpart
would have to assign a trillion times greater odds to T2 than to T1 in order for the
expected value of all the bets made by the collective of agent-parts to be zero. And yet we
argued that it seems wrong for an agent-part to assign a trillion times greater credence to
T2 than to T1.
However, this response does not address the case of the repeated Sleeping Beauty
problem. For in this case, in the infinite limit, there is no uncertainty about the total
proportion of awakenings in tails- and heads-runs of the experiment. Beauty knows that
(with probability one) there will actually be two times as many awakenings in tails-trials
as in heads-trials. In this case, therefore, betting considerations unambiguously suggest
that Beauty upon awakening should assign the 2/3 credence to tails. Here one could not
justify a divergence of credence assignment from betting odds by saying that there would
be a different number of bets placed depending on which of the hypotheses under
consideration is true, because the total number of bets placed is not (significantly)
variable when Beauty is put through a large number of repetitions of the experiment.
There is, consequently, strong reason for recommending that Beauty assign
credence 1/3 to heads when she knows that the experiment will be repeated very many
times. This, however, is not an objection to the hybrid model proposed above. The hybrid
model, as we shall now see, implies the very same credence assignment as the betting
considerations suggest. Betting considerations, far from being an embarrassment to the
hybrid model, actually agree with its implications and support it.
Up until this section, our discussion has focused on (variations of) the single-shot
Sleeping Beauty problem, where there are no repetitions of the experiment. This is the
simplest case: the world contains no other relevant agent-parts than those existing within
a single implementation of the Sleeping Beauty experiment. Let us now apply the hybrid
model to the situation that arises if the experiment is repeated many times. But first, as an
intermediary step, consider the following case.
17 See also (Arntzenius 2002).
13
Three Thousand Weeks (non-random)
Beauty lives for three thousand weeks. On odd-numbered weeks she is awakened
once, on Mondays. On even-numbered weeks she is awakened twice, on Mondays
and Tuesdays. After each awakening she is given an amnesia drug that causes her
to forget her previous awakenings. Beauty knows all this.
The hybrid model that I propose implies that in this case, Beauty should have
credence 1/3 in the centered proposition “My current awakening is taking place in an
odd-numbered week” (or “ODD” for short). This is because Beauty, when she wakes up,
knows that ODD is true for one third of all the agent-parts that are in the same subjective
evidential state as her current agent-part. (The credence assignment follows from the very
weak indifference principle which Lewis, Elga, and I all accept.) Crucially, these agentparts
are all actual agent-parts, as opposed merely possible ones. We thus have
P(ODD) = 1/3
Further, it is easy to show that
P(ODD | MONDAY) = 1/2
If we suppose that every Monday, just before being put to sleep, Beauty is told that it is
Monday, we also have
P+(ODD | MONDAY) = 1/2
Note that, for the reasons explained earlier, “MONDAY” denotes a different centered
proposition in each of these two conditional credence expressions. (In the first
expression, “MONDAY” refers to a proposition that is centered on an agent-part that
does not know that it is Monday; in the second expression, specifying Constraint P+,
“MONDAY” refers to a proposition centered on an agent-part that does know that it is
Monday.) In the present case, however, the conditional credences work out the same. The
hybrid view therefore coincides with the 1/3 view in this example.
The key difference between the original Sleeping Beauty problem and ThreeThousand
Weeks and is that in the latter case – but not in the former – there are twice as
many actual awakenings of one type as of the other. This means that in Three Thousand
Weeks, the prior credence in ODD, before Beauty learns that it is Monday, is unaffected
by the correction we made to eliminate the bias in favor of hypotheses entailing the
existence of more duplicates. (Such a bias would result from applying the indifference
principle to a class of agent-parts that included merely possible as well as actual agentparts.)
In Three-Thousand Weeks, ODD is true for one-third of the agent-parts that are
ignorant about whether it is Monday, and for one half of the agent-parts who know that it
is Monday; correspondingly, the credence in ODD is 1/3 for the first type of agent-part
and 1/2 for the second type.18
18 We say that ODD “is true for” an agent-part if the centered proposition which that agent-part would
express by saying “ODD” is true. When writing down a symbol like “ODD”, we need to be careful about
whether we take this to refer to a specific centered proposition or to a function that yields a centered
Εγγραφή σε:
Σχόλια ανάρτησης (Atom)
Δεν υπάρχουν σχόλια:
Δημοσίευση σχολίου